The piece of (street) artwork at stake in the '5 Pointz' case |
The recent decision in the 5
Pointz case [here] has brought
back to centre stage one of the quirks of US copyright law: the right to object
to any intentional or grossly negligent destruction of works of ‘recognized
stature’ (US Code,
Title 17, §106). As explained by Katfriend Mira Sundara Rajan in a recent commentary
of the case [here],
this right was introduced by the 1990 Visual Artists Rights Act (VARA) under
the umbrella doctrine of moral rights (although this right goes beyond what the
moral right doctrine traditionally entails).
From one vantage, the decision is
to be welcome, inasmuch as it protects a
notable piece of street art [per the court and mainstream
media, here and here], thereby enabling the preservation of more contemporary forms of our cultural
heritage. However, this Kat has some reservations regarding the ability of the
IP law framework to embrace such a role. In particular, who determines what is ‘recognized
stature’ and under criteria is it determined? The answer: mainly as the court
decides (read: judges), for the simple reason that Congress offered little in
the way of definition or guidance on this point [see Cheffins at 600]. This places US
judges in the difficult position of acting as cultural gatekeepers, given that
they have the final say as to what is worthy
of such protection.
Judges themselves have noted the challenge in being asked to rule on the protection
of works of recognized stature [see Martin
v City of Indiana
(1999) ; Cheffins
v Stewart
(2016)]. This
is especially so in that they are called
upon to render judgment on an issue in which they are not expected to have any necessary expertise, namely, when is a work of
"recognized stature”.
Some may argue that a concern
about judges serving as cultural gatekeepers is allayed by the fact that the context
is unique to US law and it is an unusual form of moral right. Moreover, since
few decisions are actually rendered under this provision, this risk of cultural
gatekeeping is well-contained. However, in this Kat’s view, this it is not the only occasion
in which judges are in the position of playing the part of cultural
gatekeepers. After all, copyright law applies selectively to prescribed
categories, and only these categories, of original creative works in a fixed
form – conditions which are themselves culturally-bounded [here
and here].
Furthermore, once copyright subsists in a
work, it provides a platform to control its dissemination, thereby fundamentally
impacting on the nature of our cultural landscape. Right holders, artists and
their heirs can even pursue claims bordering on strategies of ‘heritage
preservation’ or ‘heritage safeguarding’, either through the moral right
doctrine of integrity, or the economic right to control some most
derivative works, and of course, the US right to object to the destruction of
works of recognized stature. Cultural gatekeeping thus can be seen as underpinning
almost every aspect of copyright long before the right to object to the
destruction of works of ‘recognized stature’ was introduced in the US.
Thus, the larger question is how
to make sure no (or limited) cultural gatekeeping takes place there? First, we
do so by reiterating that copyright law does
not deal with cultural quality or aesthetic considerations, something both commentators
and judges in various jurisdictions (including
in the US) have often emphasised [see Gracen
at 304; Schott Musik (1997) 145 ALR 483,
486, Hensher v Restawile (1974) 2 All ER 420, 423]. In many
ways, eschewing any consideration of cultural or aesthetic quality is one of
the main safeguards within copyright law to prevent cultural gatekeeping. Indeed,
judges have been vigilant not to behave as art critics [see Bleinstein
at 251]. When they have, they have been corrected thanks to the appeal mechanism,
i.e. corrective mechanisms built into our legal systems.
A notable example was the Victor
Hugo decision (2003) in which the Court of Appeal of Paris had extended the
moral right of integrity enjoyed by Hugo’s
heirs so as to ban the publication of sequels
of Les Miserables (focusing on the
main character Jean Valjean).
The Paris Court of Appeal stated:
"… [O]utlawing
sequels of Les Miserables does not,
as the parties contend, breach the principle of free creation since, in the
facts presented before us, this work, being a
pillar of world literature. [Les
Miserables] […] is not a mere novel for it presents a philosophical and
political approach”
“Considering that,
it follows that no sequel shall ever be given to a work such as Les Miserables, forever complete, and
that the company Plon has, by editing and publishing Cosette ou Le Temps Des Illusions and Marius ou le Fugitif, by presenting the works as sequels to Les Miserables, violated Victor Hugo’s
moral right as vested in the latter literary work” [Kats’ translation]
This decision was subsequently
overturned by the Court of Cassation [here
and here],
the highest court in France for matters of civil law, which stressed that the
cultural significance of the work could not be taken into consideration in
construing the law or in balancing the fundamental rights at stake.
But are these safeguards enough?
The appeal process suffers from a major drawback: it depends upon the
claimants’ financial ability to pursue appeal proceedings. Even more, what about
more subtle cultural references made in connection with determining the
subsistence or infringement of copyright, another slippery slope of cultural
gatekeeping?
Thus, in Hadley
v Kemp (1999), Park J draw a (bold) comparison between the creative process
followed by members of the Spandau Ballet and that of Beethoven to, it seems, reach his conclusion on the difficult distinction
between authorship, joint-authorship and performership in copyright law ([1999]
EMLR 589, 645-6).
The Spandau Ballet |
The decision reads:
‘After all, when Mr
Kemp [Spandau
Ballet’s lead composer and musician] devised the song he devised it for performance, not by himself as a solo
artist, but by Mr Hadley [Spandau Ballet’s lead singer] and the whole band. A composer can ‘hear’ the sound of his composition
in his mind before he ever hears it played. Beethoven could hear his music in
this sense even when he was deaf. When Mr Kemp was devising his songs the sound
which he had in his musical consciousness must surely have been the sound they
would have when performed by Spandau Ballet, not the sound they would have when
sung by Mr Kemp alone to the accompaniment just of his own guitar.’
Why use a canon of classical
music to inform a decision on copyright about pop music marks? The analogy drawn here by the Court between
Beethoven and the Spaudau Ballet (or rather between their respective practices)
begs the question of how much this comparison weighed on the outcome of the
case. Would the court have sided with Kemp had the decision been informed by
another cultural reference, say Björk, Aretha Franklin, Daft Punk or…Kim Kardashian?
There may be a risk of indirect cultural
gatekeeping in shepherding a select few fountainheads of our culture as
relevant illustrations for the ‘hows’ and ‘whys’ of creativity for copyright
purposes. This question is particularly important when it affects the
distribution of rights between claimants or the eligibility protection of
creative expressions for copyright protection. In this regard, Hadley v Kemp is not an isolated instance (see Rockford
Map Publishers at 148-9; Miller
v Civil City of South Bend at 1093-5; Garcia
v Google at 742-3).
What could be the safeguard
against cultural gatekeeping? The answer is discussing, disputing and engaging
those who favour a select few canons of so-called ‘high-culture’ in copyright
law? To be clear— the result of this process is not predetermined. It is only
through critical inquiry that we can reach reasonable positions on whether
cultural gatekeeping and the biases that it entails, are welcome parts of the
copyright law, or is it an inevitable deviance of copyright
law-making processes?
The 5 Pointz case: a response (on the risk of cultural gatekeeping in copyright)
Reviewed by Mathilde Pavis
on
Tuesday, March 20, 2018
Rating:
No comments:
All comments must be moderated by a member of the IPKat team before they appear on the blog. Comments will not be allowed if the contravene the IPKat policy that readers' comments should not be obscene or defamatory; they should not consist of ad hominem attacks on members of the blog team or other comment-posters and they should make a constructive contribution to the discussion of the post on which they purport to comment.
It is also the IPKat policy that comments should not be made completely anonymously, and users should use a consistent name or pseudonym (which should not itself be defamatory or obscene, or that of another real person), either in the "identity" field, or at the beginning of the comment. Current practice is to, however, allow a limited number of comments that contravene this policy, provided that the comment has a high degree of relevance and the comment chain does not become too difficult to follow.
Learn more here: http://ipkitten.blogspot.com/p/want-to-complain.html